Tuesday, May 03, 2011

Choosing Hell

This post originally ran (I've cleaned up a few typos, but otherwise left it unchanged) back in 2006, but the topic has been on my mind, and having found it via Google while researching the topic of the Fundamental Option I decided to rerun this one rather than writing a new one.

Quite some time back, Pontifications ran a post about the theory of "fundamental option", which it seems is the theological term for the idea that one's salvation is based upon a fundamental choice that one makes either for or against God.

This image for the determination of one's salvation has a certain utility in that it is simple and evocative. C. S. Lewis uses it in The Last Battle, where all of Narnia's creatures face Aslan and swerve either to his right (with loving expressions) or to his left (with hate in their eyes). And yet, like any image or illustration, applying it absolutely leads to distortion. The 'encounter God and choose' image helps to emphasize that God's judgment is not some arbitrary judgment imposed upon us. It also helps to explain how someone externally appearing to have sinned many times might be saved, while someone who to all appearances led a virtuous life, yet held pride in his heart, might reject God and be condemned. And yet, taken as an absolute of 'salvation by choice alone' the theory of 'fundamental option' becomes just as much a heresy as 'salvation by faith alone'.

John Paul II said as much in Veritas Splendor:
To separate the fundamental option from concrete kinds of behavior means to contradict the substantial integrity or personal unity of the moral agent in his body and in his soul. A fundamental option understood without explicit consideration of the potentialities which it puts into effect and the determinations which express it does not do justice to the rational finality immanent in mans acting and in each of his deliberate decisions.
It is keeping this integrity between the human agent's identity, will and action that is the difficult balance for most of us, I think. Our culture tends to think of each choice as a totally free activity. Thus, the idea of experiencing for an instant the clarity of the Beatific Vision and in that instant choosing for or against God seems like an isolated decision point, unencumbered by past decisions. Indeed, some use this view to support the claim that perhaps all will be saved, because no one (when truly seeing God for what He is) would reject Him.

And yet, classic Christian moral theology does not support this view of total personal freedom. Virtue is often described as 'the habit of doing good' while attachment to sin is that moral habit which, once one has sinned, makes it hard to make the right choice in the future. Thus, the first time you lie in order to get out of a difficult situation, you struggle to make it come out convincingly and fear for days that your lie will be found out. But with each transgression the lie comes more naturally, until it becomes nearly impossible to tell the truth in a difficult situation -- the convenient lie comes out without even thinking.

It is because we are changed as moral agents by our past choices that our fundamental choice for or against God at the particular judgment cannot be divorced from the moral decisions we have made throughout our lives. Each time we sin or resist sin, makes it harder or easier to make that decision at the moment of personal judgment.

Perhaps, as in so many other things, the analogy of marriage is useful. One can, as a moral agent, choose at any given point in one's marriage to do something that is good for or bad for one's spouse. And yet, a given man with a given history can make it harder or easier to treat his wife well by building a history of good or bad behavior. While, in theory, a man who has lied and mistreated and been unfaithful to his wife can still, at any given decision point, choose to treat her well, he has vastly decreased both his ability to treat his wife well, and also his knowledge of what his wife truly wants, and thus his ability to treat her well even if he wants to.

3 comments:

  1. That is helpful. I've had difficulties understanding how it could be said to have free will given the consequences: Hell is worse than a loaded gun, and yet if someone holds a gun to our head and tells us to give them our money, that is said to be coercive and that our free will has been removed in that instance.

    ReplyDelete
  2. I've always found the description of salvation vs. damnation as a "fundamental option" useful. Rather than leaving it as a "mere choice," being wrong for the reasons you pointed out, I always thought it just made sense to give this "choice" a rich construction; i.e. the choice we make at judgment is not a one-off event, but is conditioned by all our previous choices in favor of or against virtue. This also helps to explain how one retains free will even though they will no longer be able to sin after salvation, because they've been brought to this state through their own choice for virtue.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Actually, "fundamental option" in proportionalist ethical reasoning isn't separate from individual deeds. It's more like your life-orienting factor: that end which you are seeking. Acts lead to habits that build character, which is the inculcation of virtues that help us to our end.

    That said, the real problem with proportionalism is in the notion of "premoral values," because they tend to play down the absolute nature of "exceptionless norms." I'm not quite clear on whether proportionalists actually support that position. It seems that they combine material and formal norms into synthetic norms that are pretty much absolute and exceptionless. I think they have been trying to firm up their theory to respond to Blessed JPII's and Pope Benedict's criticisms. However, I'll stick with the traditional reasoning until it's clear that the proportionalists have cleaned up their act and have brought their theory inline with Magisterial teaching.

    ReplyDelete